UseTactics: Tactic Library for CoqA Gentle Introduction

(* Chapter written and maintained by Arthur Chargueraud *)
Coq comes with a set of builtin tactics, such as reflexivity, intros, inversion and so on. While it is possible to conduct proofs using only those tactics, you can significantly increase your productivity by working with a set of more powerful tactics. This chapter describes a number of such useful tactics, which, for various reasons, are not yet available by default in Coq. These tactics are defined in the LibTactics.v file.
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing,-deprecated-hint-without-locality".

From Coq Require Import Arith.Arith.

From PLF Require Maps.
From PLF Require Stlc.
From PLF Require Types.
From PLF Require Smallstep.
From PLF Require LibTactics.
From PLF Require Equiv.
From PLF Require References.
From PLF Require Hoare.
From PLF Require Sub.

Import LibTactics.
Remark: SSReflect is another package providing powerful tactics. The library "LibTactics" differs from "SSReflect" in two respects:
  • "SSReflect" was primarily developed for proving mathematical theorems, whereas "LibTactics" was primarily developed for proving theorems on programming languages. In particular, "LibTactics" provides a number of useful tactics that have no counterpart in the "SSReflect" package.
  • "SSReflect" entirely rethinks the presentation of tactics, whereas "LibTactics" mostly stick to the traditional presentation of Coq tactics, simply providing a number of additional tactics. For this reason, "LibTactics" is probably easier to get started with than "SSReflect".
This chapter is a tutorial focusing on the most useful features from the "LibTactics" library. It does not aim at presenting all the features of "LibTactics". The detailed specification of tactics can be found in the source file LibTactics.v. Further documentation as well as demos can be found at https://www.chargueraud.org/softs/tlc/.
In this tutorial, tactics are presented using examples taken from the core chapters of the "Software Foundations" course. To illustrate the various ways in which a given tactic can be used, we use a tactic that duplicates a given goal. More precisely, dup produces two copies of the current goal, and dup n produces n copies of it.

Tactics for Naming and Performing Inversion

This section presents the following tactics:
  • introv, for naming hypotheses more efficiently,
  • inverts, for improving the inversion tactic.

The Tactic introv

Module IntrovExamples.

Import Maps.
Import Imp.
Import Equiv.
Import Stlc.
The tactic introv allows to automatically introduce the variables of a theorem and explicitly name the hypotheses involved. In the example shown next, the variables c, st, st1 and st2 involved in the statement of determinism need not be named explicitly, because their name where already given in the statement of the lemma. On the contrary, it is useful to provide names for the two hypotheses, which we name E1 and E2, respectively.
Theorem ceval_deterministic: c st st1 st2,
  st =[ c ]=> st1
  st =[ c ]=> st2
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  introv E1 E2. (* was intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2 *)
Abort.
When there is no hypothesis to be named, one can call introv without any argument.
Theorem dist_exists_or : (X:Type) (P Q : X Prop),
  ( x, P x Q x) ( x, P x) ( x, Q x).
Proof.
  introv. (* was intros X P Q *)
Abort.
The tactic introv also applies to statements in which and are interleaved.
Theorem ceval_deterministic': c st st1,
  (st =[ c ]=> st1)
   st2,
  (st =[ c ]=> st2)
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  introv E1 E2. (* was intros c st st1 E1 st2 E2 *)
Abort.
Like the arguments of intros, the arguments of introv can be structured patterns.
Theorem exists_impl: X (P : X Prop) (Q : Prop) (R : Prop),
  ( x, P x Q)
  (( x, P x) Q).
Proof.
  introv [x H2]. eauto.
  (* same as intros X P Q R H1 [x H2]., which is itself short
     for intros X P Q R H1 H2. destruct H2 as [x H2]. *)

Qed.
Remark: the tactic introv works even when definitions need to be unfolded in order to reveal hypotheses.

The Tactic inverts

Module InvertsExamples.
Import Maps.
Import Imp.
Import Equiv.
The inversion tactic of Coq is not very satisfying for three reasons. First, it produces a bunch of equalities which one typically wants to substitute away, using subst. Second, it introduces meaningless names for hypotheses. Third, a call to inversion H does not remove H from the context, even though in most cases an hypothesis is no longer needed after being inverted. The tactic inverts address all of these three issues. It is intented to be used in place of the tactic inversion.
The following example illustrates how the tactic inverts H behaves mostly like inversion H except that it performs some substitutions in order to eliminate the trivial equalities that are being produced by inversion.
Theorem skip_left: c,
  cequiv <{skip; c}> c.
Proof.
  introv. split; intros H.
  dup. (* duplicate the goal for comparison *)
  (* was... *)
  - inversion H. subst. inversion H2. subst. assumption.
  (* now... *)
  - inverts H. inverts H2. assumption.
Abort.
A slightly more interesting example appears next.
Theorem ceval_deterministic: c st st1 st2,
  st =[ c ]=> st1
  st =[ c ]=> st2
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  introv E1 E2. generalize dependent st2.
  induction E1; intros st2 E2.
  admit. admit. (* skip some basic cases *)
  dup. (* duplicate the goal for comparison *)
  (* was: *)
  - inversion E2. subst. admit.
  (* now: *)
  - inverts E2. admit.
Abort.
The tactic inverts H as. is like inverts H except that the variables and hypotheses being produced are placed in the goal rather than in the context. This strategy allows naming those new variables and hypotheses explicitly, using either intros or introv.
Theorem ceval_deterministic': c st st1 st2,
  st =[ c ]=> st1
  st =[ c ]=> st2
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  introv E1 E2. generalize dependent st2.
  induction E1; intros st2 E2;
    inverts E2 as.
  - (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
  - (* E_Asgn *)
    (* Observe that the variable n is not automatically
       substituted because, contrary to inversion E2; subst,
       the tactic inverts E2 does not substitute the equalities
       that exist before running the inversion. *)

    (* new: *) subst n.
    reflexivity.
  - (* E_Seq *)
    (* Here, the newly created variables can be introduced
       using intros, so they can be assigned meaningful names,
       for example st3 instead of st'0. *)

    (* new: *) intros st3 Red1 Red2.
    assert (st' = st3) as EQ1.
    { (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
    subst st3.
    apply IHE1_2. assumption.
  (* E_IfTrue *)
  - (* b1 reduces to true *)
    (* In an easy case like this one, there is no need to
       provide meaningful names, so we can just use intros *)

    (* new: *) intros.
    apply IHE1. assumption.
  - (* b1 reduces to false (contradiction) *)
    (* new: *) intros.
    rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
  (* The other cases are similiar *)
Abort.
In the particular case where a call to inversion produces a single subgoal, one can use the syntax inverts H as H1 H2 H3 for calling inverts and naming the new hypotheses H1, H2 and H3. In other words, the tactic inverts H as H1 H2 H3 is equivalent to inverts H as; introv H1 H2 H3. An example follows.
Theorem skip_left': c,
  cequiv <{ skip ; c}> c.
Proof.
  introv. split; intros H.
  inverts H as U V. (* new hypotheses are named U and V *)
  inverts U. assumption.
Abort.

End InvertsExamples.
A more involved example appears next. In particular, this example shows that the name of the hypothesis being inverted can be reused.
Module InvertsExamples1.
Import Types.
Import Stlc.
Import STLC.
Import Maps.

Example typing_nonexample_1 :
  ¬ T,
      empty |--
        \x:Bool,
            \y:Bool,
               (x y) \in
        T.
Proof.
  dup 3.

  (* The old proof: *)
  - intros Hc. destruct Hc as [T Hc].
  inversion Hc; subst; clear Hc.
  inversion H4; subst; clear H4.
  inversion H5; subst; clear H5 H4.
  inversion H2; subst; clear H2.
  discriminate H1.

  (* The new proof: *)
  - intros C. destruct C.
  inverts H as H1.
  inverts H1 as H2.
  inverts H2 as H3 H4.
  inverts H3 as H5.
  inverts H5.

  (* The new proof, alternative: *)
  - intros C. destruct C.
  inverts H as H.
  inverts H as H.
  inverts H as H1 H2.
  inverts H1 as H1.
  inverts H1.
Qed.

End InvertsExamples1.
Note: in the rare cases where one needs to perform an inversion on an hypothesis H without clearing H from the context, one can use the tactic inverts keep H, where the keyword keep indicates that the hypothesis should be kept in the context.

Tactics for N-ary Connectives

Because Coq encodes conjunctions and disjunctions using binary constructors and , working with a conjunction or a disjunction of N facts can sometimes be quite cumbursome. For this reason, "LibTactics" provides tactics offering direct support for n-ary conjunctions and disjunctions. It also provides direct support for n-ary existententials.
This section presents the following tactics:
  • splits for decomposing n-ary conjunctions,
  • branch for decomposing n-ary disjunctions
Module NaryExamples.
  Import References.
  Import Smallstep.
  Import STLCRef.

The Tactic splits

The tactic splits applies to a goal made of a conjunction of n propositions and it produces n subgoals. For example, it decomposes the goal G1 G2 G3 into the three subgoals G1, G2 and G3.
Lemma demo_splits : n m,
  n > 0 n < m m < n+10 m 3.
Proof.
  intros. splits.
Abort.

The Tactic branch

The tactic branch k can be used to prove a n-ary disjunction. For example, if the goal takes the form G1 G2 G3, the tactic branch 2 leaves only G2 as subgoal. The following example illustrates the behavior of the branch tactic.
Lemma demo_branch : n m,
  n < m n = m m < n.
Proof.
  intros.
  destruct (lt_eq_lt_dec n m) as [ [H1|H2]|H3].
  - branch 1. apply H1.
  - branch 2. apply H2.
  - branch 3. apply H3.
Qed.

End NaryExamples.

Tactics for Working with Equality

One of the major weaknesses of Coq compared with other interactive proof assistants is its relatively poor support for reasoning with equalities. The tactics described next aims at simplifying pieces of proof scripts manipulating equalities.
This section presents the following tactics:
  • asserts_rewrite for introducing an equality to rewrite with,
  • substs for improving the subst tactic,
  • fequals for improving the f_equal tactic,
  • applys_eq for proving P x y using an hypothesis P x z, automatically producing an equality y = z as subgoal.

The Tactic asserts_rewrite

The tactic asserts_rewrite (E1 = E2) replaces E1 with E2 in the goal, and produces the goal E1 = E2.
Theorem mult_0_plus : n m : nat,
  (0 + n) × m = n × m.
Proof.
  dup.
  (* The old proof: *)
  intros n m.
  assert (H: 0 + n = n). reflexivity. rewriteH.
  reflexivity.

  (* The new proof: *)
  intros n m.
  asserts_rewrite (0 + n = n).
    reflexivity. (* subgoal 0+n = n *)
    reflexivity. (* subgoal n×m = n×m *)
Qed.
Remark: the syntax asserts_rewrite (E1 = E2) in H allows rewriting in the hypothesis H rather than in the goal.
More generally, the tactic asserts_rewrite can be provided a lemma as argument. For example, one can write asserts_rewrite ( a b, a*(S b) = a×b+a). This formulation is useful when a and b are big terms, since there is no need to repeat their statements.
Theorem mult_0_plus'' : u v w x y z: nat,
  (u + v) × (S (w × x + y)) = z.
Proof.
  intros. asserts_rewrite ( a b, a*(S b) = a×b+a).
    (* first subgoal:   a b, a*(S b) = a×b+a *)
    (* second subgoal: (u + v) × (w × x + y) + (u + v) = z *)
Abort.
The tactic cuts_rewrite is similar to asserts_write except that it the two subgoals produced are swapped.

The Tactic substs

The tactic substs is similar to subst except that it does not fail when the goal contains "circular equalities", such as x = f x.
Lemma demo_substs : x y (f:natnat),
  x = f x
  y = x
  y = f x.
Proof.
  intros. substs. (* the tactic subst would fail here *)
  assumption.
Qed.

The Tactic fequals

The tactic fequals is similar to f_equal except that it directly discharges all the trivial subgoals produced. Moreover, the tactic fequals features an enhanced treatment of equalities between tuples.
Lemma demo_fequals : (a b c d e : nat) (f : natnatnatnatnat),
  a = 1
  b = e
  e = 2
  f a b c d = f 1 2 c 4.
Proof.
  intros. fequals.
  (* subgoals a = 1b = 2 and c = c are proved, d = 4 remains *)
Abort.

The Tactic applys_eq

The tactic applys_eq is a variant of eapply that introduces equalities for subterms that do not unify. For example, assume the goal is the proposition P x y and assume we have the assumption H asserting that P x z holds. We know that we can prove y to be equal to z. So, we could call the tactic assert_rewrite (y = z) and change the goal to P x z, but this would require copy-pasting the values of y and z. With the tactic applys_eq, we can call applys_eq H, which proves the goal and leaves only the subgoal y = z.
Axiom big_expression_using : natnat. (* Used in the example *)

Lemma demo_applys_eq_1 : (P:natnatProp) x y z,
  P x (big_expression_using z)
  P x (big_expression_using y).
Proof.
  introv H. dup.

  (* The old proof: *)
  assert (Eq: big_expression_using y = big_expression_using z).
    admit. (* Assume we can prove this equality somehow. *)
  rewrite Eq. apply H.

  (* The new proof: *)
  applys_eq H.
    admit. (* Assume we can prove this equality somehow. *)
Abort.
When we have a mismatch on two arguments, the tactic applys_eq produces two equalities. Consider the following example.
Lemma demo_applys_eq_2 : (P:natnatProp) x1 x2 y1 y2,
  P (big_expression_using x2) (big_expression_using y2)
  P (big_expression_using x1) (big_expression_using y1).
Proof.
  introv H. applys_eq H.
  (* produces two subgoals:
     big_expression_using x1 = big_expression_using x2
     big_expression_using y1 = big_expression_using y2 *)

Abort.

End EqualityExamples.

Some Convenient Shorthands

This section of the tutorial introduces a few tactics that help make proof scripts shorter and more readable:
  • unfolds (without argument) for unfolding the head definition,
  • false for replacing the goal with False,
  • gen as a shorthand for generalize dependent,
  • admits for naming an admitted fact,
  • admit_rewrite for rewriting using an admitted equality,
  • admit_goal to set up a proof by induction by skipping the justification that some order decreases,
  • sort for re-ordering the proof context by moving all propositions at the bottom.

The Tactic unfolds

Module UnfoldsExample.
  Import Hoare.
The tactic unfolds (without any argument) unfolds the head constant of the goal. This tactic saves the need to name the constant explicitly.
Lemma bexp_eval_true : b st,
  beval st b = true
  (bassn b) st.
Proof.
  intros b st Hbe. dup.

  (* The old proof: *)
  unfold bassn. assumption.

  (* The new proof: *)
  unfolds. assumption.
Qed.
Remark: contrary to the tactic hnf, which may unfold several constants, unfolds performs only a single step of unfolding.
Remark: the tactic unfolds in H can be used to unfold the head definition of the hypothesis H.

The Tactics false and tryfalse

The tactic false can be used to replace any goal with False. In short, it is a shorthand for exfalso. Moreover, false proves the goal if it contains an absurd assumption, such as False or 0 = S n, or if it contains contradictory assumptions, such as x = true and x = false.
Lemma demo_false : n,
  S n = 1
  n = 0.
Proof.
  intros. destruct n. reflexivity. false.
Qed.
The tactic false can be given an argument: false H replace the goals with False and then applies H.
Lemma demo_false_arg :
  ( n, n < 0 False)
  3 < 0
  4 < 0.
Proof.
  intros H L. false H. apply L.
Qed.
The tactic tryfalse is a shorthand for try solve [false]: it tries to find a contradiction in the goal. The tactic tryfalse is generally called after a case analysis.
Lemma demo_tryfalse : n,
  S n = 1
  n = 0.
Proof.
  intros. destruct n; tryfalse. reflexivity.
Qed.

The Tactic gen

The tactic gen is a shortand for generalize dependent that accepts several arguments at once. An invocation of this tactic takes the form gen x y z.
Module GenExample.
  Import Stlc.
  Import STLC.
  Import Maps.

Lemma substitution_preserves_typing : Gamma x U t v T,
  x > U ; Gamma |-- t \in T
  empty |-- v \in U
  Gamma |-- [x:=v]t \in T.
Proof.
  dup.

  (* The old proof: *)
  - intros Gamma x U t v T Ht Hv.
  generalize dependent Gamma. generalize dependent T.
  induction t; intros T Gamma H;
    inversion H; clear H; subst; simpl; eauto.
  admit. admit.

  (* The new proof: *)
  - introv Ht Hv. gen Gamma T.
  induction t; intros S Gamma H;
    inversion H; clear H; subst; simpl; eauto.
  admit. admit.
Abort.

End GenExample.

The Tactics admits, admit_rewrite and admit_goal

Temporarily admitting a given subgoal is very useful when constructing proofs. Several tactics are provided as useful wrappers around the builtin admit tactic.
Module SkipExample.
The tactic admits H: P adds the hypothesis H: P to the context, without checking whether the proposition P is true. It is useful for exploiting a fact and postponing its proof. Note: admits H: P is simply a shorthand for assert (H:P). admit.
Theorem demo_admits : True.
Proof.
  admits H: ( n m : nat, (0 + n) × m = n × m).
Abort.
The tactic admit_rewrite (E1 = E2) replaces E1 with E2 in the goal, without checking that E1 is actually equal to E2.
Theorem mult_plus_0 : n m : nat,
  (n + 0) × m = n × m.
Proof.
  dup 3.

  (* The old proof: *)
  intros n m.
  assert (H: n + 0 = n). admit. rewriteH. clear H.
  reflexivity.

  (* The new proof: *)
  intros n m.
  admit_rewrite (n + 0 = n).
  reflexivity.

  (* Remark: admit_rewrite can be given a lemma statement as argument,
   like asserts_rewrite. For example: *)

  intros n m.
  admit_rewrite ( a, a + 0 = a).
  reflexivity.
Admitted.
The tactic admit_goal adds the current goal as hypothesis. This cheat is useful to set up the structure of a proof by induction without having to worry about the induction hypothesis being applied only to smaller arguments. Using skip_goal, one can construct a proof in two steps: first, check that the main arguments go through without waisting time on fixing the details of the induction hypotheses; then, focus on fixing the invokations of the induction hypothesis.
Import Imp.
Theorem ceval_deterministic: c st st1 st2,
  st =[ c ]=> st1
  st =[ c ]=> st2
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  (* The tactic admit_goal creates an hypothesis called IH
     asserting that the statment of ceval_deterministic is true. *)

  admit_goal.
  (* Of course, if we call assumption here, then the goal is solved
     right away, but the point is to do the proof and use IH
     only at the places where we need an induction hypothesis. *)

  introv E1 E2. gen st2.
  induction E1; introv E2; inverts E2 as.
  - (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
  - (* E_Asgn *)
    subst n.
    reflexivity.
  - (* E_Seq *)
    intros st3 Red1 Red2.
    assert (st' = st3) as EQ1.
    { (* Proof of assertion *)
      (* was: apply IHE1_1; assumption. *)
      (* new: *) eapply IH. eapply E1_1. eapply Red1. }
    subst st3.
    (* was: apply IHE1_2. assumption. *)
    (* new: *) eapply IH. eapply E1_2. eapply Red2.
  (* The other cases are similiar. *)
Abort.

End SkipExample.

The Tactic sort

Module SortExamples.
  Import Imp.
The tactic sort reorganizes the proof context by placing all the variables at the top and all the hypotheses at the bottom, thereby making the proof context more readable.
Theorem ceval_deterministic: c st st1 st2,
  st =[ c ]=> st1
  st =[ c ]=> st2
  st1 = st2.
Proof.
  intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2.
  generalize dependent st2.
  induction E1; intros st2 E2; inverts E2.
  admit. admit. (* Skipping some trivial cases *)
  sort. (* Observe how the context is reorganized *)
Abort.

End SortExamples.

Tactics for Advanced Lemma Instantiation

This last section describes a mechanism for instantiating a lemma by providing some of its arguments and leaving others implicit. Variables whose instantiation is not provided are turned into existentential variables, and facts whose instantiation is not provided are turned into subgoals.
Remark: this instantion mechanism goes far beyond the abilities of the "Implicit Arguments" mechanism. The point of the instantiation mechanism described in this section is that you will no longer need to spend time figuring out how many underscore symbols you need to write.
In this section, we'll use a useful feature of Coq for decomposing conjunctions and existentials. In short, a tactic like intros or destruct can be provided with a pattern (H1 & H2 & H3 & H4 & H5), which is a shorthand for [H1 [H2 [H3 [H4 H5] ] ] ] . For example, destruct (H _ _ _ Htypt) as [T [Hctx Hsub]]. can be rewritten in the form destruct (H _ _ _ Htypt) as (T & Hctx & Hsub).

Working of lets

When we have a lemma (or an assumption) that we want to exploit, we often need to explicitly provide arguments to this lemma, writing something like: destruct (typing_inversion_var _ _ _ Htypt) as (T & Hctx & Hsub). The need to write several times the "underscore" symbol is tedious. Not only we need to figure out how many of them to write down, but it also makes the proof scripts look prettly ugly. With the tactic lets, one can simply write: lets (T & Hctx & Hsub): typing_inversion_var Htypt.
In short, this tactic lets allows to specialize a lemma on a bunch of variables and hypotheses. The syntax is lets I: E0 E1 .. EN, for building an hypothesis named I by applying the fact E0 to the arguments E1 to EN. Not all the arguments need to be provided, however the arguments that are provided need to be provided in the correct order. The tactic relies on a first-match algorithm based on types in order to figure out how the to instantiate the lemma with the arguments provided.
Module ExamplesLets.

(* To illustrate the working of lets, assume that we want to
   exploit the following lemma. *)


Import Maps.
Import Sub.STLCSub.
Import String.

Axiom typing_inversion_var : Gamma (x:string) T,
  Gamma |-- x \in T
   S,
    Gamma x = Some S S <: T.
First, assume we have an assumption H with the type of the form has_type G (var x) T. We can obtain the conclusion of the lemma typing_inversion_var by invoking the tactics lets K: typing_inversion_var H, as shown next.
Lemma demo_lets_1 : (G:context) (x:string) (T:ty),
  G |-- x \in T
  True.
Proof.
  intros G x T H. dup.

  (* step-by-step: *)
  lets K: typing_inversion_var H.
  destruct K as (S & Eq & Sub).
  admit.

  (* all-at-once: *)
  lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var H.
  admit.
Abort.
Assume now that we know the values of G, x and T and we want to obtain S, and have has_type G (var x) T be produced as a subgoal. To indicate that we want all the remaining arguments of typing_inversion_var to be produced as subgoals, we use a triple-underscore symbol ___. (We'll later introduce a shorthand tactic called forwards to avoid writing triple underscores.)
Lemma demo_lets_2 : (G:context) (x:string) (T:ty), True.
Proof.
  intros G x T.
  lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var G x T ___.
Abort.
Usually, there is only one context G and one type T that are going to be suitable for proving has_type G (tm_var x) T, so we don't really need to bother giving G and T explicitly. It suffices to call lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var x. The variables G and T are then instantiated using existential variables.
Lemma demo_lets_3 : (x:string), True.
Proof.
  intros x.
  lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var x ___.
Abort.
We may go even further by not giving any argument to instantiate typing_inversion_var. In this case, three unification variables are introduced.
Lemma demo_lets_4 : True.
Proof.
  lets (S & Eq & Sub): typing_inversion_var ___.
Abort.
Note: if we provide lets with only the name of the lemma as argument, it simply adds this lemma in the proof context, without trying to instantiate any of its arguments.
Lemma demo_lets_5 : True.
Proof.
  lets H: typing_inversion_var.
Abort.
A last useful feature of lets is the double-underscore symbol, which allows skipping an argument when several arguments have the same type. In the following example, our assumption quantifies over two variables n and m, both of type nat. We would like m to be instantiated as the value 3, but without specifying a value for n. This can be achieved by writting lets K: H __ 3.
Lemma demo_lets_underscore :
  ( n m, n m n < m+1)
  True.
Proof.
  intros H.

  (* If we do not use a double underscore, the first argument,
     which is n, gets instantiated as 3. *)

  lets K: H 3. (* gives K of type  m, 3 m 3 < m+1 *)
    clear K.

  (* The double underscore preceeding 3 indicates that we want
     to skip a value that has the type nat (because 3 has
     the type nat). So, the variable m gets instiated as 3. *)

  lets K: H __ 3. (* gives K of type ?X 3 ?X < 3+1 *)
    clear K.
Abort.
Note: one can write lets: E0 E1 E2 in place of lets H: E0 E1 E2. In this case, the name H is chosen arbitrarily.
Note: the tactics lets accepts up to five arguments. Another syntax is available for providing more than five arguments. It consists in using a list introduced with the special symbol >>, for example lets H: (>> E0 E1 E2 E3 E4 E5 E6 E7 E8 E9 10).

Working of applys, forwards and specializes

The tactics applys, forwards and specializes are shorthand that may be used in place of lets to perform specific tasks.
  • forwards is a shorthand for instantiating all the arguments
of a lemma. More precisely, forwards H: E0 E1 E2 E3 is the same as lets H: E0 E1 E2 E3 ___, where the triple-underscore has the same meaning as explained earlier on.
  • applys allows building a lemma using the advanced instantion
mode of lets, and then apply that lemma right away. So, applys E0 E1 E2 E3 is the same as lets H: E0 E1 E2 E3 followed with eapply H and then clear H.
  • specializes is a shorthand for instantiating in-place
an assumption from the context with particular arguments. More precisely, specializes H E0 E1 is the same as lets H': H E0 E1 followed with clear H and rename H' into H.
Examples of use of applys appear further on. Several examples of use of forwards can be found in the tutorial chapter UseAuto.

Summary

In this chapter we have presented a number of tactics that help make proof script more concise and more robust on change.
  • introv and inverts improve naming and inversions.
  • false and tryfalse help discarding absurd goals.
  • unfolds automatically calls unfold on the head definition.
  • gen helps setting up goals for induction.
  • splits and branch, to deal with n-ary constructs.
  • asserts_rewrite, cuts_rewrite, substs and fequals help working with equalities.
  • lets, forwards, specializes and applys provide means of very conveniently instantiating lemmas.
  • applys_eq can save the need to perform manual rewriting steps before being able to apply a lemma.
  • admits, admit_rewrite and admit_goal give the flexibility to choose which subgoals to try and discharge first.
Making use of these tactics can boost one's productivity in Coq proofs.
If you are interested in using LibTactics.v in your own developments, make sure you get the lastest version from: https://www.chargueraud.org/softs/tlc/.
(* 2023-10-01 07:21 *)